Universität Wien

180695 SE Thinking in Groups (2011S)

Contemporary Perspectives on Group Cognition in Philosophy, Psychology, and the Social Sciences

6.00 ECTS (2.00 SWS), SPL 18 - Philosophie
Continuous assessment of course work

Die Teilnahme an meinem Seminar bietet Studierenden die Möglichkeit zur Absolvierung einer philosophischen Lehrveranstaltung in einer lebenden Fremdsprache.

Registration/Deregistration

Note: The time of your registration within the registration period has no effect on the allocation of places (no first come, first served).

Details

max. 25 participants
Language: English

Lecturers

Classes (iCal) - next class is marked with N

Wednesday 02.03. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 09.03. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 16.03. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 23.03. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 30.03. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 06.04. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 13.04. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 04.05. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 11.05. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 18.05. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 25.05. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 01.06. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 08.06. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 15.06. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 22.06. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock
Wednesday 29.06. 12:00 - 14:00 Hörsaal 3E NIG 3.Stock

Information

Aims, contents and method of the course

Many philosophers share the strong intuition that mental or cognitive properties should be attributed at exactly one level of organization: the individual organism. In particular, individual human beings are considered to be the paradigmatic subjects of mental properties. However, many highly prized activities in our species are accomplished only when we think and act together in groups. Can a group constitute a cognitive system—a mind—in its own right?

The so-called “group mind” thesis was a popular fixture in the intellectual landscape of the late 19th and early 20th century (Wilson, 2004). It crystallized the idea of a group as a collective agent, and its gestalt as an emergent whole that is more than the sum of its parts. To its own detriment, many traditional formulations of this idea remained highly speculative and often bordered on the occult. As a result, the “group mind” concept quickly fell out of favor with the rise of behaviorism in psychology, since it remained unclear where the “group mind” was supposed to reside, and how we could measure it (Wegner, 1986). One way to summarize the precarious ontological status of group minds is in the form of the following dilemma. If the group mind is nothing over and above the collection of individual minds and their interactions, an appeal to group minds appears to be redundant. However, if the group mind is something over and above all these things, it appears to imply a collective version of mind-body dualism. This raises the familiar question of how the group mind exercises its causal influence on group members. Some bizarre answers were suggested in response to this problem, such as the putative mediation of a genetic “ectoplasm” (Jung, 1922) or telepathic communication (McDougall, 1920). In sum, neither horn of the dilemma makes the idea of group minds seem very attractive.

However, roughly fifty years after the “cognitive revolution” in psychology, the idea that groups can have cognitive properties of their own has gained new ascendancy in a wide range of disciplines concerned with group behavior. Rather than engaging in abstract arguments about the possibility of “group minds,” contemporary appeals to group cognition have typically tied their claims to particular kinds of psychological predicates. For instance, social psychologists studying memory, problem-solving, and decision-making in small groups have based their work on a view of groups as adaptive information-processing systems in their own right (Wegner et al., 1985; Cicourel, 1990; Larsen & Christensen, 1993; Hinsz et al., 1997; Propp, 1999; Stasser, 1999; Mohammed & Dumville, 2001; Lewis, 2003; Goldstone & Gureckis, 2009). Organizational scientists have studied the memory and learning processes of firms and organizations (Sandelands & Stablein, 1987; Walsh & Ungson, 1991; Argote, 1999). Sociologists, anthropologists, and historians have found it useful to express generalizations about social groups in terms of their collective memory (Burke, 1989; Le Goff, 1992). Economists and political scientists continue to explore the relationships between individual and group rationality in the arena of judgment aggregation (Pettit, 2003; List, 2003, 2010). Evolutionary biologists have revived the idea that groups can evolve into adaptive units of cognition as a result of group-selection (D.S. Wilson, 1997, 2002; D.S. Wilson, van Vugt, & O’Gorman, 2008). Recent studies of animal behavior have revealed a number of collective decision-making mechanisms that are shared across a wide range of group types such as swarming ants, schooling fish, flocking birds, and also humans (Hölldobler & E.O. Wilson, 1990; Seeley, 1995; Bonabeau, Dorigo, & Theraulaz, 1999; Couzin, 2009). The framework of distributed cognition has been used to study the dynamics of collaborative work practices which are socially, technologically, and temporally distributed, and whose coordination is mediated by rich situational, material, and organizational constraints. (Hutchins, 1995a, 1995b; Hollan, Hutchins, & Kirsh, 2000). The framework of distributed cognition has recently been embraced by some philosophers of science as a unifying framework to overcome the present hiatus between “rationalist” and “social-constructionist” approaches to scientific cognition (Giere, 2002, 2005; Giere & Moffat, 2003; Nersessian, 2006). The term “crowdsourcing” has been coined to describe ways of leveraging Web 2.0 technologies for the purposes of mass collaboration (Howe, 2006; Shirky, 2008). Finally, philosophers seeking a conceptual analysis of collective intentionality—such as collective beliefs, intentions, and responsibilities—have tied their accounts to the recognition of groups as intentional subjects in their own right (Gilbert, 1989; Velleman, 1997; Schmitt, 2003; Tollefsen, 2004; List, 2010).

Underlying the current revival of group cognition is the idea that groups have an organizational structure which arises from social interactions between people, together with the concrete material context in which their interactions take place. This structure determines the patterns in which information is represented, propagated and transformed through group activities. If the social patterns of information-processing are sufficiently stable, they can be said to reflect a kind of cognitive architecture of the group. The social and material organization of groups thus underpins their capacity to perform a variety of tasks—e.g. attention, learning, memory, the formation of beliefs, reasoning, and decision-making—that we would clearly recognize as cognitive if they were performed by individuals. Of course this does not imply that groups always solve the same cognitive problems as its members, or that groups solve cognitive problems in the same way that individuals do. It only means that group cognition is not just the unstructured aggregation of individual cognition, but stems from a division of cognitive labor among individual agents. Sometimes, that division is the result of an explicit organizational design imposed by a central planning agency, such as the hierarchical structure found in large business corporations. But perhaps more commonly, adaptive group structures can arise from purely local interactions between many individuals without their express intent, and sometimes without even being noticed by those individuals.

The potential of complex systems to display organization-dependent properties that its lower-level components do not have, and that in turn affect the behavior of those components, is often discussed under the rubric of emergence (Holland, 1975, 1995; Kauffman, 1993; Ball, 1998; Stephan, 1999; Sawyer, 2005). But since emergence is a notoriously ambiguous notion, an important goal of this course will be to flesh out what it can plausibly be taken to mean in the context of group cognition. As we shall see, many traditional versions of the “group mind” thesis—as well as objections by its critics—have rested on inadequate conceptions of the micro-macro link between individuals and groups. A better philosophical understanding of multi-level ontologies will thus help us clear the ground before we can liberate the cognate notions of agency, mind, and cognition from their individualistic shackles.

Assessment and permitted materials

A student’s final course grade will be determined holistically on the basis of his/her overall performance in the following categories:

1. About ten short, weekly responses to assigned course readings, including peer commentary, to be submitted online (via Moodle) in advance to our class meetings
2. Active class participation, including a group presentation
3. A focused reaction piece [~4-5 pages] on a selected course topic
4. A research proposal/outline of their term paper [~4-5 pages], due before the end of the semester
5. A term paper [~3,000-3,500 words]

Minimum requirements and assessment criteria

Students with an interest in this seminar should be prepared to wrestle with some difficult but philosophically rewarding issues, such as: what kind of “ontological commitments” do we incur when we attribute mental states and processes to groups? What kinds of cognitive properties (if any) can groups possess; and how do they differ from the cognitive properties of the individuals who act in those groups? Is group cognition an emergent phenomenon, or can it be reductively analyzed in terms of individual cognition (and what exactly does that mean?) What is the nature of explanations which refer to group cognition, and how can they be squared with explanations at lower levels of organization? What kinds of properties must groups have to be considered as collective agents?

In trying to answer these questions, we will get a chance to reflect carefully on the eminent significance which thinking and acting in groups plays for our species. This exhortation comes with the sincere warning that taking this course may seriously erode traditional individualist prejudices on where to locate mind and cognition in a comprehensive picture of the world. Our frequent engagement with a diverse body of empirical literature originating outside academic philosophy will also provide us with ample opportunity to consider matters of philosophical methodology and its status vis-a-vis the social and cognitive sciences.

Examination topics

I plan to run the course in the style of a typical seminar, structured mostly by presentations interspersed and followed-up with lots of vigorous discussion. For the first half of the course, I will assume primary responsibility for presenting the relevant material. This not only serves the purpose of supplying students with the necessary background knowledge to follow the current debate, but also to establish a shared vantage point (anchored, broadly speaking, in the Analytic tradition) from which we can profitably frame our discussion. Later in the semester, a number of our meetings will be reserved for group presentations. Occasionally, we may just have a free discussion of the readings, or engage in small-group assignments.

In order to foster the development of critical writing skills, students will be asked to perform several types of writing assignments. First, in advance of our class meetings, students post weekly commentaries on the assigned readings in an online discussion forum (Moodle). Typically, two students serve as primary commentators for a given week, while all others act as secondary commentators, responding to the issues which the primary commentators have raised. Second, students will be asked to hand in a short, focused reaction piece on a course topic of their choice. Finally, students will have a chance to conduct their own research in the form of a term paper. To facilitate and monitor students’ progress, everybody will first go through a mandatory draft stage. This means that towards the end of the semester, each student will submit his/her research proposal, including a detailed outline of their paper, and meet with me to discuss their plans for the final paper. The final paper will be due in accordance with university regulations.

Reading list

Course readings will be made available either online (Moodle) or in a designated Handapparat.

Association in the course directory

MA M 3, § 4.1.4 und § 2.5

Last modified: Mo 07.09.2020 15:36